Skip to content
A practical theory of international politics

Executive Summary

This essay proposes a practical theory of international politics. The basic points are:

  • The form politics takes is primarily determined by the tension levels between the States involved - friends cooperate, rivals compete, and enemies fight.1
  • Tension levels determine the means of power/threat States use and the logic of their interaction. E.g. friendly neighbours can’t use military threats against each other and stay friends, just like military enemies are past trade disputes and sanctions.
  • The escalation of tension levels happens in predictable, concrete steps and is fairly well researched. I use Friedrich Glasl’s nine-step-model of conflict escalation model to illustrate.
  • Unsuccessful uses of power/threats is the primary way conflicts escalate.
  • Institutions and treaties are designed to withstand a certain maximum level of tension. If tensions escalate beyond their dispute settlement mechanisms, these structures falter or break down.

I believe the theory laid out here is superior to current theories in several respects:

  • It is more accurate - and empirically falsifiable to begin with
  • It is useful to practitioners who need a strong framework of analysis
  • It leads researchers to ask better research questions.

What is politics?

As a starting point, it’s difficult to disagree with Andrew Heywood’s introductory definition that politics is “the activity through which people make, preserve and amend the general rules under which they live.”2 I’ll use “make the general rules” as a shorthand.

Heywood’s introduction goes on to differentiate four categories of definitions: Politics understood as (1) the art of government (think Bismarck, Machiavelli, Easton, and arguably Clausewitz) and politics as (2) public affairs (Aristotle, Mill, Rousseau, Arendt, the liberal tradition more generally); politics as (3) compromise and consensus (Habermas, Crick), and politics as (4) power and the distribution of resources (Leftwich, Lasswell, realism, often feminism and Marxism).

Politics without the State?

The first two differ mainly on whether or not politics happens when the State isn’t involved. To define politics as the art of government is an institutional definition. It’s similar to Clausewitz’ definition of warfare as ‘everything that is related to the armed forces; their creation, maintenance and use.’3 So, labour relations, gender identity, religious obligations, or beauty standards; are these issues ‘political’ even when they don’t involve the State?

I don’t think this question should be predefined in general terms for all societies throughout history. Instead, let’s extrapolate from Heywood’s initial definition: Whether or not politics is that which pertains to the State depends on whether for the given issue, place and time, States are used to set the ‘general rules’. If it’s other institutions (e.g. the workplace, religious institutions, tribal clan structures, international organizations, et cetera), then the process by which those ‘general rules’ are set is political, too, and our theory should yield insights for it.

Politics without power?

Heywood’s latter two groups disagree mostly about whether politics also happens when nobody imposes their will on somebody else. When everybody freely agrees on a reasonable general rule, is that still politics?

As we shall see, it is largely correct that power is usually a key ingredient in politics. And it is also true that using power is anathema to friendship. But to then say politics is defined as that which involves power and rivalry is effectively to assume that setting general rules cooperatively – as happens in most households around the globe on a daily basis – is humanely impossible, or too boring to think about. As Sir Bernard Crick put it: ‘Why call … a struggle for power ‘politics’ when it is simply a struggle for power?’4

What is power?

Power is commonly defined as control: A has power over B if A can make B do what A wants.5 Hans J. Morgenthau elaborated: “Power may comprise anything that establishes and maintains the power of man over man. Thus power covers all social relationships which serve that end, from physical violence to the most subtle psychological ties by which one mind controls another.”6

Power looking backward and forward in time

An interesting property of this definition is that one can only say whether A has power over B after A has successfully used that power. In other words: The definition does not actually define anything that makes a State powerful vis-à-vis another State. It defines the effect you’ll see when you look back in time - namely, that thing which will have made B do what A wants.7 The means that will achieve this control isn’t predefined – if anything, it’s post-defined. My martial arts skills do not give me in and of themselves power over you, only once I successfully used them to threaten you into giving me your ice cream can we potentially say that they give me power over you.

Repeated and institutionalised interaction diminishes this problem. But let’s stick with simple power for the time being. In this realm, to know beforehand whether or not you’ll submit to the threat of my martial arts skills is somewhere between an art and a science. The reason is that it is you who chooses to submit or not. In the moment right after I issued my threat, it’s your cost-benefit calculation that counts, not mine. So it may be that you’re a judo master and confident that you could beat me easily. Even then, maybe to you the hassle just isn’t worth an ice cream. It requires some knowledge about the other party to know which threats they may yield to.

And if you choose not to submit and violence breaks out? Well, as Morgenthau (and many, many others) knew: “When violence becomes an actuality, it signifies the abdication of political power in favour of military or pseudo-military power.”6 If you consider that A essentially tries to control B’s behaviour, you immediately see that if A has to resort to brute physical force to do so (what Morgenthau called ‘military power’) that must mean that B’s behaviour wasn’t successfully controlled.

This generalises: As I shall now argue, looking forward in time, power is successful threat of sorts. The really interesting thing a theory of power should do is to try and predict the means of threat/power that States will marshal…

PS: I don’t have any martial arts skills.

Predicting the means of power/threat

This part can be thought of as an update to Morgenthau’s view of human nature (you find more about his view in the academic part at the end). It’s based on the insight that the tension level between parties foreshadows before-the-fact which means of threat they will use if they choose to use power against each other. In short: Power is a successful threat with a higher tension level - often the next higher level.

That’s why it’s utterly unbecoming to a friendship to attempt to use power - because you essentially threaten your friends with conflict escalation. Likewise it’s irrelevant if you threaten an enemy with an angry letter - because the relationship is long past that point. The means I can reasonably be expected to use to attempt to control you depend on whether you are my friend, my rival, or my enemy.

For any individual act, we can ask: Given the current relationship and its tension level, is this act escalatory, de-escalatory, or confirming the status quo?

This same way we also determine how extreme an act is. If Macron were to buy Schultz an ice-cream as a friendly gesture, that’d be slightly awkward, but basically confirming that they are friends. Yet, if Putin bought him an ice-cream, he’d (quite rightly) have it tested. Little details that are irrelevant among relaxed friends can become very important status symbols between tense enemies – like when Yasser Arafat and Ehud Barak couldn’t decide who enters the door first at Camp David.

In conflict research and social psychology, a great deal of research has been conducted into the nature of conflict escalation and de-escalation - a field I propose political analysts should tap into. How tensions escalate and friends become enemies is actually quite well understood, predictable and known in considerable detail. I shall now give a fairly detailed overview.

Basic logic of conflict escalation

This account uses a popular model of conflict escalation from the German conflict research literature to present the evidence – Friedrich Glasl’s Konfliktmanagement.8 He proposes a detailed nine step model of conflict degeneration (or escalation) in which the relationship of two or more parties slowly disintegrates from a mild hardening of positions to a total war of mutual obliteration.

On each step of the ladder, the parties intuitively know which kind of behaviour is adequate and what constitutes a taboo. But because conflicts are very frustrating situations for us humans to be in, there is a tendency in each party on each step to try to dissolve the distressing ambiguity of the situation. And, one way we ironically choose is breaking the next taboo-barrier.

”Crossing points of no return [taboo-barriers] thus means that one has reached a more intense stage of conflict. This new stage has its own norms, regiment and rules. But it is again clearly delineated by a new barrier. And precisely this barrier gives the parties – in spite of a heightened use of violence – new securities! Violence does not become limitless in a bang, but is again constrained. … The expectations remain – like Tomas Schelling says – co-ordinated.”9

With these distinct steps we can deduce what means of power can be expected to be marshalled on each step. Indeed, as we shall see, this perspective utterly reframes the very nature of power as such.

There is no state of nature

For the present purposes it shall suffice to collate the nine steps of Glasl’s staircase into three spheres (following Glasl himself):

  • On steps one to three, the parties’ perception is still issue-oriented and they share a win-win mentality, they are friends.
  • On steps four to six their perception is person-oriented and they have a win-lose mentality, they are rivals.
  • And on steps seven to nine their perception is destruction-oriented and they have a lose-lose mentality, they are enemies.

There three spheres roughly correspond to the way Alexander Wendt read Martin Wight’s ‘three cultures of anarchy’ in his Social Theory of International Relations– Kantian, Lockean and Hobbesian. ‘[A]t the core of each kind of anarchy is just one subject position: In Hobbesian cultures it is “enemy,” in Lockean “rival,” and Kantian “friend.”’10 But Glasl’s work, as we shall see, is much better rooted in research and adds considerable depth and detail. Also, crucially, it explains the dynamics of change.

The brief sketch that follows paints a picture of an ideal-type conflict degeneration without any conflict resolving forces in order to illustrate it. Nothing here suggests that the ‘normal’ state of human affairs – the null hypothesis – is conflict-free or peaceful, or that human societies teleologically gravitate towards cooperation.11 Indeed, I agree with Glasl: While conflict escalation is driven to a great degree by primitive, partly unconscious drives, conflict de-escalation is usually a conscious, laborious, and rational effort.12 Overall, there simply is no state of nature; we possess the capacity for cooperation, rivalry, or violence.

1-3 - Friends: ‘We have a problem’

Through the first three steps (the Kantian sphere of cooperation), the parties involved think in terms of issues. The sovereignty and physical integrity of the other participants is not only guaranteed, rather, it is so deeply internalised that the parties don’t even think about the possibility of violating it. For example, Switzerland ‘accidentally invaded’ neighbouring Liechtenstein in 2007 (170 infantry soldiers unknowingly crossed the unmarked border.13 Nobody doubted this was an accident and a simple apology sufficed to make amends. Imagine the same scenario on the Lebanese-Israeli border.

Nevertheless, absent an apology or other conflict resolving forces, the conflict will begin to polarise the parties’ thinking, feeling or willing.14

  • An initial hardening of positions and behavioural patterns (step 1) gives way to debates and polemics15 (step 2) when a party deliberately and consistently uses (polemic or behavioural) tactics to win the argument rather than to discuss the issue. That’s the first taboo-barrier from step one to two (henceforth abbreviated like this: ‘taboo-barrier 1>2’).
  • Then, when the parties start using unilateral actions to confront the other party with a fait accompli (taboo-barrier 2>3), the conflict escalates to the third step, where the parties believe that ‘actions speak louder than words!’16 (step 3).
  • The last taboo-barrier to be broken upon becoming rivals and entering the Lockean sphere is the profound shift from an issue- to a person-orientated perception, when one party deliberately and consistently attacks the other ad hominem (taboo-barrier 3>4). The parties’ conviction that they are friends with an issue to solve is obliterated. ‘Thomas Gordon called this: From act (a disturbing action) to actor (a disturbing person)!’17

4-6 - Rivals: ‘You are a problem’

The increasing importance of self- and other-image already anticipates the primacy of personal identity throughout Lockean power politics.

  • Initially (step 4), the parties worry about their reputation and honour.18 The next taboo-barrier is broken when a party wilfully provokes the public loss of face of the rival (4>5).
  • In their struggle for their reputation (their ‘face’), the parties seek to convert bystanders of their other-images of the rival (step 5).19 The parties might now start to use punitive violence in a discernibly restricted manner – often in ways that can later be repudiated. Their frustration leads the parties to paradoxically seek to assert their independence by using (step 6) strategies involving threat and coercion (‘taboo-barrier 5>6’)20: We’ve seen that unilateral actions have been used from step three onwards and grown more and more extreme, up to the punitive violence from step five. What now occurs is the following: The previous unilateral acts were past-oriented (‘You did X, therefore I now do Y!’), but now the parties being to use clear, irrevocable threats which in contrast are future-oriented (‘If you do X, I will do Y!’). However, the (quite logical) effect of such threats is the exact opposite of independence, because the parties essentially surrender their agency to their rival. Also, ‘[t]hese threat-strategies work only so long as it is clear that they are intended to avert a greater escalation of violence.’21
  • But the parties sooner or later begin to threaten with the violation of the other’s physical sovereignty which fundamentally shakes the parties’ sense of physical security. Enacting such a threat and violating the other party’s physical sovereignty (‘taboo-barrier 6>7’) makes Lockean rivals become Hobbesian enemies and the conflict escalates into the Hobbesian sphere of war.

Conflict escalation through the Lockean sphere defines the alliances which will fight against each other in the subsequent Hobbesian struggle by totalising the self- and other image across all aspects of life and making their division absolute. Interestingly, ‘to a striking degree, the misperceptions of those in conflict are mutual’22 – an effect which is called negative mirror-image perceptions.23 This makes sense in the following way: Both parties need to justify to themselves the same frustrating state of affairs and – according to Glasl and the theory outlined here – they both create mental models with clear self- and other-images that absolve them of their part of responsibility in creating the status quo. The primacy of these identities creates considerable in-group cohesion24 and lets members’ individual identities become more and more irrelevant.25 They also increase the profound suspicion (step 4) to an autistic enmity (step 5 and 6) and finally profound hatred (step 7). Under these psychological pressures, the parties now seek to find loopholes in established norms that allow them to hurt the other party without openly violating the norm.26

7-9 - Enemies: ‘You threaten my existence’

The importance of physical security and threats towards the end of the Lockean rivalry already anticipates the primacy of the means of violence in the Hobbesian sphere. The enemy’s loss is now considered a direct personal gain in and of itself (nicely captured in the German Schadenfreude). For example, ‘[in the nuclear-war planning of the cold-war era] the calculation went, if each side was likely to suffer 50% or even 75% casualties among its entire population, the war would be ‘won’ in ensuing years by the side that could more quickly recover, rebuild (and repopulate).’27 In other words, the logic of the situation is no longer zero-sum but negative-sum.

  • The parties now typically attempt to permanently destroy the capability with which the other party threatened them on previous steps. They attempt a restricted final blow,28 aimed at disabling the threat the other party poses without destroying the other party completely. But even if this is the initial aim of destructive violence, it is not always possible to disable the threat decisively enough. Thus, eventually, the application of violence broadens in the next step when the parties begin to target the enemy’s central nervous system.29 In war this would be the moment a party begins to target the civilian infrastructure. They shoot to kill the other party as such.
  • If neither party destroys the other in this total war, the one last barrier that can be crossed is the kamikaze mentality: ‘[The parties] lash about senselessly because they experience slithering towards an abyss from which there is no escape. Their only solace is to drag their enemy down along with them so that the enemy has to perish too.’30

The shift from Locke to Hobbes coincides with a shift from rivalry to war – again with Morgenthau: ‘When violence becomes an actuality, it signifies the abdication of political power in favour of military or pseudo-military power.’31 Delivering on the promises made at the end of the Lockean sphere in the form of threats (step 6), in the Hobbesian sphere both parties aim, from the beginning, at the lasting destruction of the enemy’s capability that is threatening them. As one security analyst put it in the context of the Iran-Israel crisis:

“Generally in war, targeters look much wider than specific targets, at what makes those targets important and how they can be rapidly replaced. Targeting post-attack recovery capabilities is standard practice with emphasis on personnel.”32

But the parties do not leap into an all-out war right away, and powerful tacit agreements underpin the Hobbesian stage too (step 7).33 For example, Kane and Lonsdale argue that the common Clausewitzian assertion that ‘war is the continuation of political intercourse with the admixture of other means’34 rests on the consequentialist ethics that ‘military power is only valid if it serves the interests of the community…’35 – which is maybe a little too optimistic a reading of Clausewitz, but serves to make the point.

Morgenthau too argues against Waltz’ claim that States in anarchy cannot afford to be moral – Kane and Lonsdale summarise his position thus:

“Reducing a rival’s population would diminish an important source of [its] relative power. However, certainly in peacetime, and even in most wars, States do not enact such a policy. The reason for this, Morgenthau argues, is that there is an agreed moral position among States on the value of civilian life.”36

The particular insight of Glasl is that the shift from step seven to eight obliterates these basic moral principles. The very category ‘civilian’ is obliterated and population centres become fair game.37

Resumé

So, if one looks back at Glasl’s conflict degeneration ladder, one can summarise that

”The worsening of the parties’ communication aggravates their negative attitudes from mistrust to profound suspicion (2-4) up to an autistic enmity (5-6) and finally bottomless hatred (6-8), which can end in self-hatred.”38

Part of this degeneration is the corrosion of established norms.

”Initially, established norms [e.g. sovereignty] are fully recognised and the parties beware of violating them. Later (4-5) they attempt to find loopholes they can exploit and use against the other party without openly violating the norm. Afterwards (6-8), they care little about norms and accordingly violate them if they stand in their way.”39

I’d add that this corrosion of established norms is often accompanied by the emergence of a primitive tribal morality.

Observe that of these three spheres, only fully-degenerated Hobbesian enemies lash out at each other according to the logic of total struggle. As such ‘[they] cannot count on each other for help or even to observe basic self-restraint’40 – ultimately, as we’ve seen, not even on the self-restraint induced by self-preservation. Wendt is quite right that such ‘lack of inhibition and self-restraint in Hobbesian cultures suggests that balances of power there will be difficult to sustain’41 because States would attack at every single opportunity.

Offensive realism is thus actually not quite as Hobbesian as it might portray itself to be. ‘Sovereignty is the ground rule of inter-State relations in that it identifies the territorial entities [which] are eligible to participate in the game.’42 If States acted towards one another the way Hobbes claimed individuals act in the state of nature, or the way offensive realists claim States behave, they would never respect, let alone establish, the modern ground rule of international politics: territorial sovereignty.

Indeed, it is important to stress that the behavioural logic at such high tension levels is often unrestrained even by elementary tactical thinking. If you agree with Clausewitz that defence is a stronger form of war than attack,43 well, that alone would undermine offensive realism. But it doesn’t: Because the insanity of offensive realism actually exists at high tension levels. There, parties are quite happy to die to win and are generally unreasonable.

A new understanding of power

I said before that power is always a successful threat using means from higher tension levels. Now we have pretty solid idea of what that means and can attempt a before-the-fact approximation of the means of power/threat parties will use to try to control somebody – the after-the-fact definition of power we usually use in political science.

Say tensions are already on step four, where the parties worry primarily about their reputation and honour. If somebody wanted to use power against somebody else in this context, the additional means of power/threat they’d now most likely employ would be threatening to release some dirty secrets about their rival to cause her or his loss of face. This while continuing to employ all previous means of power/threat already used.

This view of power alone, I think, already provides us with a straightforward research agenda for political science in general and IR in particular. We should study and catalogue the specific means of power/threat parties (for IR mostly States) tend to use at which tension levels. If catalogued, this would additionally provide us with data for network analyses: If actors A and B have an escalating conflict, when and how do they involve actor C? (The guess is from stage five onwards.) How do the tension levels between A and C, or B and C, influence this? Whereas Kenneth Waltz’ crude notion of material capability didn’t lead to knowledge accumulation (and in my opinion positively obscured it), this could provide a more realistic backbone for research.

There is little reason to constrain such research to political science only: We’ve seen the main insights in this part came not from our own field at all, but from conflict research and psychology. Indeed, while the groundwork for this theory might already touch on many aspects of political science, it itself still consists mostly of claims about human psychology. So far, it really is just an update of Morgenthau’s view of human nature.

I invoke ‘human nature’ not to unduly and dogmatically root a competitive urge in humans and thus explain politics (a very common misinterpretation of Morgenthau). There exists no universal proactive competitive or violent urge in humans. There exists a universal competitive and violent potential in humans which can be provoked – along the steps outlined above.

Footnotes

  1. Academics will recognize Alexander Wendt’s cultures of anarchy. But this account goes beyond Wendt. Wendt, Alexander. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

  2. Heywood, Andrew. Politics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007. 4.

  3. Clausewitz, Carl Philipp Gottlieb von. Vom Kriege. Edited by J. Schulze. 1 edition. Null Papier Gratis, 1832. chap. 2.

  4. Crick, Bernard. In Defence of Politics. New Ed edition. London: Continuum, 2005. p. 5.

  5. Dahl is (unjustly) often credited with the original complete formulation, Dahl, Robert A. ‘The Concept of Power’. Behavioral Science 2, no. 3 (1957): 201–15. https://doi.org/10.1002/bs.3830020303. For alternatives and a comprehensive taxonomy of power definitions in IR, see Barnett, Michael, and Raymond Duvall. ‘Power in Global Governance’. In Power in Global Governance, edited by Michael Barnett and Raymond Duvall, 98:1–32. Cambridge University Press, 2004. Influential studies of political power work with this definition are, e.g., Dahl, Robert A. Who Governs?: Democracy And Power In An American City. Yale University Press, 2005; Lindblom, Charles Edward. Politics and Markets: The World’s Political Economic Systems. Basic Books, 1977.

  6. Morgenthau, Hans Joachim. Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace. Edited by Kenneth W. Thompson. Knopf, 1985. 2

  7. It’s worth noting that, even in retrospect, it’s not entirely clear what made B give in.

  8. Glasl, Friedrich. Konfliktmanagement : Ein Handbuch Für Führungskräfte, Beraterinnen Und Berater. Bern: Haupt Verlag, 2010.

  9. Glasl 2010, 230.

  10. Wendt 1999, 258. More generally chap. 6.

  11. In fact, after reading some of Stephen Pinker’s work, I think such a view is rather difficult to entertain. Especially, Pinker, Steven. The Better Angels of Our Nature: A History of Violence and Humanity. London: Penguin, 2012. Also Pinker, Steven. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. New York: Penguin, 2003.

  12. Glasl 2010, 197–8. Also consider Nelson Mandela: ‘Our talking to the enemy was the result of the domination of the brain over emotion.’ Nelson Mandela: ‘We Made the Brain Dominate the Blood’ - Oprah Winfrey Network 2013.

  13. Oliver, Mark, and agencies. ‘Liechtenstein: No Retaliation for Swiss “Invasion”’. The Guardian, 2 March 2007, sec. World news. http://www.theguardian.com/world/2007/mar/02/markoliver.

  14. Glasl 2010, 234–9.

  15. Ibid., 239–49.

  16. Ibid., 249–56.

  17. Glasl, Friedrich. ‘AW: Klärungsfrage [Personal Communication]’, 19 March 2012.

  18. Glasl 2010, 256–66.

  19. Ibid., 266–77.

  20. Ibid., 277–92.

  21. Ibid., 292.

  22. Myers, David G, and Jean M Twenge. Social Psychology. 10th ed. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill, 2013.

  23. Ibid.

  24. Gibler, D. M. shows that external threats, especially when territorial, produce a rallying effect behind a country’s leader(s). Gibler, Douglas M. ‘Outside-In: The Effects of External Threat on State Centralization’. Journal of Conflict Resolution 54, no. 4 (8 January 2010): 519–42. https://doi.org/10.1177/0022002710370135.

  25. Young, S. G. et al. show that a racial intergroup context hampers facial recognition for both in- and out-group. See, Young, Steven G., Kurt Hugenberg, Micheal J. Bernstein, and Donald F. Sacco. ‘Interracial Contexts Debilitate Same-Race Face Recognition’. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45, no. 5 (September 2009): 1123–26. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2009.05.009.

  26. Glasl 2010, 301.

  27. Rogers, Paul. ‘Israel and Iran: After the Bombs Fall’. openDemocracy (blog), 5 April 2012. http://www.opendemocracy.net/paul-rogers/israel-and-iran-after-bombs-fall.

  28. Glasl 2010, 292–7.

  29. Ibid., 297–9.

  30. Ibid., 299–300.

  31. Morgenthau 1985, 31.

  32. In the case of Israel targeting Iran’s nuclear capability, this means targeting “advanced training facilities and their staff, especially relevant university centres, as well as research and development centres for both the nuclear and missile programmes.” Rogers, Paul. ‘The Potential for Israeli Military Action against Iran’s Nuclear Facilities’. Oxford Research Group (blog), 1 March 2012. http://www.oxfordresearchgroup.org.uk/publications/middle_east/potential_israeli_military_action_against_iran%E2%80%99s_nuclear_facilities.

  33. Snyder observes that norms underpinning the state-centric realist paradigm act as ‘system modifiers.’ Snyder, Glenn H. ‘Process Variables in Neorealist Theory’. Security Studies 5, no. 3 (1996): 167–92. https://doi.org/10.1080/09636419608429279.

  34. By their translation. Kane, Thomas M, and David J Lonsdale. Understanding Contemporary Strategy. Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY: Routledge, 2012, 2.

  35. Ibid., 48.

  36. Ibid., based on Morgenthau 2007.

  37. As outlined for nuclear attack plans in Kahn and Jones 2007.

  38. Glasl 2010, 300. Obviously bad communication is not necessarily the main cause of conflict – not all conflict is ‘just’ a misunderstanding.

  39. Ibid., 301.

  40. Wendt 1999, 265.

  41. Ibid., 266.

  42. James, Alan. ‘Sovereignty: Ground Rule or Gibberish?’ Review of International Studies 10, no. 01 (1984): 1–18. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0260210500116018. 2.

  43. Clausewitz 1832, ch. 1, sec. 1.16. This frustrated Clausewitz because defence serves only a negative purpose: preservation. In Clausewitz’ view, ‘if defence has a negative object, it follows that it should be used only so long as weakness compels and be abandoned as soon as we are strong enough to pursue a positive object’. Gat, Azar. ‘Clausewitz on Defence and Attack’. Journal of Strategic Studies 11, no. 1 (1 March 1988): 20–26. https://doi.org/10.1080/01402398808437327. 20.